Thursday, January 16, 2020

Commitment

Part 1: Public Commitment

The Structure of Commitment

To begin I would like to present a model of commitment. Commitment is the restriction of one’s freedom or potentiality in order to achieve some end. All acts by their very nature are commitments to something instead of something else. We are, as humans, always fundamentally acting towards some end or projecting towards a possible state of affairs[1], which entails that we are not free to do otherwise in that act. Only in acting (and in no other way) do we make transparent what our commitments actually are. For example, the amount one gets out and swims, cycles, and runs is a commitment to being able to finish or participate in a triathlon. Likewise, failing to undertake this training is itself a commitment towards (probably) not finishing or participating in a triathlon. While this is somewhat obvious, where it becomes interesting is the interaction between verbal enunciations of said commitments (which is still an act) and the credibility of it as a signal, perceived by others.

All acts (even negatively defined) are fundamentally acts towards some end instead of another; this is commitment.


Verbal Commitments as Signals

In order to make clear our intentions and communicate with others in everyday living, we make proclamations such as “I will do x", for example. We do this not to substitute the more concrete form of acting and doing, but to be economic with our time or to signal to others that we are a certain kind of person that does certain things, without having to actually go out and do them in front of people. We could hardly function as we do at without these verbal shortcuts.

The unfortunate part about it though is that verbal commitments have the peculiar translucency that means that they can overstate or understate what one’s actual commitments are. In other words, verbal commitments have the power to claim much more or less than their action actually entails. This gives rise to a serious problem: people can, at low cost, deploy verbal commitment to imitate greater commitment than one is comfortably willing to restrict their freedom for. Ask yourself why we often dismiss politicians’ verbal commitment to policy change as disingenuous, they can say whatever they want and often we see no substantial change (whether there is a change or not). Why? Because verbal commitments alone fail the “costly-to-fake principle.”[2] It states that signals fail to be credible if they are easy or cost-free to fake. There arises a need to test the validity of verbal commitments according to their context and whether they map to a person’s prior action.

Verbal commitments are a social shortcut in which we can signal commitments, but are low-cost and easily imitated, meaning we require a criterion for credibility.


Commitment Criterion

As a result of the imitation problem, the effectiveness of a verbal commitment regresses back to either (a) the context of such an utterance, and the extent to which the one restricts their own freedom in doing so or (b) whether that person (in the observer’s mind) has appropriately demonstrated their commitment already through prior action. Not unless some part of you visibly incurs some risk, or, actually tightens their potentiality for future freedoms and possibilities can it be genuine.

(a)   Verbal Commitment in Context
Remember our politician friend. Most people fail to see many claims of theirs as credible as it is not like their job or livelihood is at risk if they fail to come through with it – they have no ‘skin in the game.’[3] On the other hand, take a public verbal denunciation of the state in mainland China. This is a powerful commitment through ‘mere’ verbalization, not because she just claims it to be, but because in doing so she makes it credible by risking punishment in the form of imprisonment or death. The context of a verbal commitment can itself be the grounds for making credible one’s commitments.

(b)   Verbal Commitment Measured against Prior Action
The other way in which verbal commitments are made credible is by measuring it against prior action. An example of this is those publicly “committed” to preventing climate change. It is very easy to gauge actual levels of commitment on this issue. There are those who substantially change their diet, use their vote to attempt to enact change, use reusable containers, cups, and bags and at every point they can. And there are those who post long Instagram stories of ironic signs at climate marches yet still fail to make any sort of real change in their life that restricts what they already do. The greater one is willing to, and has, risked their freedom for their commitments the more credible they become.

What is common in these cases that commitment transcends mere words. Concrete action provides a much firmer basis for signaling what one’s commitments truly are.[4] As discussed at the start, all actions are the sole designator of commitment. You are not committed to donating to charity if you don’t donate to charity, nor can you claim not to be committed to donate charity if you consistently do.


The credibility of verbal commitments as signals is determined by risk (as the continued pursuit of one end at the expense of others) incurred within the context.

Public commitment credibility maps proportionally to how much one is willing to incur risk (restrict their potentiality) in pursuit of the commitment.



A Word on Signal Relativism

The way I have been talking about it makes it sound like there is a hard and fast way of determining ‘true’ commitment from false, but this is not true. There are virtually endless possibilities about how an action will be interpreted by observers due to our differing psychology and priors. The credence signals are given are therefore in some sense relative. For example, take the politician. Their claim to bring about prosperity will likely be taken as highly credible by those already predisposed to that politicians’ goals, party, or ideology. A sworn enemy will see it as baseless platitudes or even literal lies.

A crucial distinction to be made here though is the relativism of the verbal and the concrete commitment. A verbal commitment due to its failure to track actual commitment and ease to imitate means that, by its very nature, it can be interpreted and taken in an endless variety of ways. Concrete determinate action leaves much less room for interpretation. While a political speech can be interpreted in an endless variety of ways that lead to accusations of lying, dog-whistles, or even profundity means there aren’t totally valid ways of assessing such a speech. On the other hand, a politician actually making good (or bad) on their promises gives us a better sense in which we can validate commitments. The number of houses built under ‘Kiwibuild’ is a better measure of government commitment to housing than the verbal election promises made. A suspected unfaithful husband claiming commitment to their spouse means credibility is up in the air, walking in on him having sex with someone else says a whole lot more about his actual commitment.

The credibility of a commitment is relative to the observer, but the concrete action leaves much less to be interpreted than the verbal commitment.


A Case Study: Judah's Folly

I think some scenes from Woody Allen’s Crimes and Misdemeanors are particularly relevant. Martin Landau’s character cheats on his wife and claims that he “promised her nothing” which he may not have verbally – but he questions whether his actions say otherwise. I mean, he spent two years scheming behind his wife’s back to be with her. That’s going to say a lot more than any verbal commitment will. They both spent that time with each other, rather than pursuing other ends (sacrificing their potentiality). Landau’s character is constantly trying to tell himself, and his mistress, that it was never like that but the credibility of that crumbles when she thinks back to all that time spent together. That being said the mistress could clearly see he had not left his wife after all this time (contrary to his claims) and ought to have known his true commitment to her was never going to be what she wanted.

This is a case of Judah under determining commitment verbally as a way of rationalising the relationship to himself, but also overdetermining in the sense that he said enough to keep her on the line but never fully committed to her.










[1] Heidegger’s notion of “Care” is the influence here.
[2] Robert Frank’s book Passions Within Reasons discusses this.
[3] From Nicholas Nassim Taleb's Skin in the Game.
[4] What is called revealed preferences in economics is like this. It says that actual purchasing habits provide a better ground for predictions than rational utility or self-report, as concrete action is a stronger signal of commitment to what consumers want.

3 comments:

  1. Below is a respone by my Aunty Phillipa, read it! She has made me realise the baggage that comes along with the word commitment - it perhaps conjures up something I don't exactly mean. Commentary to keep in mind.

    "Firstly, yes I think that the concept of ‘commitment’ is very productive, in my opinion, particularly for the connections and disruptions that emerge between individual and collective capacity for commitment, and access to power, and/or empowerment (slightly different things). Above all, the capacity to make a commitment requires access to material, cognitive, and social resources (including freedom of mobility and speech per community and family norms, adequate education so as to be able to accurately judge the quality of information being offered, the support of peers, teachers, religious leaders, workplace norms) all of which are differentially enabled (and disabled) by sociological variables of class, gender, sexuality, ethnicity, status, age, geocultural location etc.

    I speculate that it is only once these variables are taken into account, that it becomes possible to accurately measure the opportunity costs of making commitments: for example, media magnate Rupert Murdoch’s recent commitment to donate $5 million to ameliorate the effects of Australia’s bush fire crisis is infinitely less onerous to him personally than are the commitments being made in the same cause by individuals who comprise ‘University Students for Climate Change,’ who work voluntarily to raise funds, organise information sharing, and protest events.

    Secondly, to your point about verbal commitments as signals, I worry about the sense that ‘commitment’ is synonymous with ‘do or die’ and start to feel the need for a spectrum of alternative concepts that might (or might not) be more precisely appropriate to any given situation. Of them, my favourite alternative to the concept of commitment is that of ‘promise;’ its etymology includes the idea that we ‘allow something to go forward’ and this is relatively open to the need we all face from time to time, to change our minds about things; as the ‘controversial’ Australian theologian Desmond Ford once famously remarked: ‘to change your mind is the best evidence that you have one.’ That he is controversial is a gateway clue to the tacit assumptions about power that are carried by the concept of commitment.

    Thirdly, and to your point about commitment criterion; reading through reminds me of points of contract law, also the protocols of risk management, especially for emergency services; these clear materially observable examples bring the need for a fully developed, mature, political science analysis of the concept of commitment to the fore. Again, ideas about promise, possibility, opportunity, and creative play are also all important, in other words, I’m not certain that I agree with you (as you say and I’m not 100 per cent certain what you mean) that ‘all actions are the sole designator of commitment.’ BUT if the development and application of policy is to be sustainable and beneficial, it is crucial that commitments are made, but equally crucial, imo, that they are only ever made as the final step of, and in accordance with, first-order-of-priority processes of research, consultation, respectful recognition of everyone involved or influenced, asking questions, listening respectfully to answers, researching answers, asking more questions, careful planning, and allowing adequate time for reflection on all contingencies. Posts to instagram etc might seem facile and many are, but are also part of what comprises these processes, probably in particular the memes that provoke revulsion, there are always questions to unpack about why). Sure, scrolling through twitter isn’t the same as making a ‘do or die’ commitment though we know some trolls actually do this. But for everyone else who isn’t actually insane, social media engagement is one part of those important background thinking and research processes that should precede any commitment."

    ReplyDelete
  2. In order to clear up what I mean its probably worth replying to a point of the comment above:

    "Again, ideas about promise, possibility, opportunity, and creative play are also all important, in other words, I’m not certain that I agree with you (as you say and I’m not 100 per cent certain what you mean) that ‘all actions are the sole designator of commitment.’ BUT if the development and application of policy is to be sustainable and beneficial, it is crucial that commitments are made, but equally crucial, imo, that they are only ever made as the final step of, and in accordance with, first-order-of-priority processes of research, consultation, respectful recognition of everyone involved or influenced, asking questions, listening respectfully to answers, researching answers, asking more questions, careful planning, and allowing adequate time for reflection on all contingencies."

    This - I totally agree with. I guess in hindsight commitment, as you rightly point out, implies a sort of (perhaps political) action that is world changing. But when I use commitment I mean it to subsume all of the above possibilities. All of those actions I am just calling commitment. Research etc. is still a sign of commitment. This also points perhaps to the weakness of my mention about kiwibuild i.e. the failure to give results doesn't mean they aren't committed.

    Also: I think she is right in pointing out my maybe undue cynicism about social media activism. It really has pulled through in important ways in the past.

    Thanks again for the Response :)

    ReplyDelete
  3. "Care, as a primordial structural totality, lies 'before' ["vor"] every factical 'attitude' and 'situation' of Dasein, and it does so existentially a priori; this means that it always lies in them. So this phenomenon by no expresses a priority to the 'practical' attitude over the theoretical. When we ascertain something present-at-hand by merely beholding it, this activity has the character of care just as much as does a 'political action' or taking a rest and enjoying oneself. 'Theory' and 'practice' are possibilities of Being for an entity whose Being must be defined as "care"." - A clarifying passage from Heidegger.

    ReplyDelete