This is the second essay in my series, The Phenomenological Papers, a series of essays on similar topics. You can find the first essay here. Like the first, this is also an old essay that I have substantively revised, so much so, in fact, that the original is unrecognisable in it. This, and the next essay, will be on something I have long been preoccupied with: the experience of art. Not totally happy with the formulation, but I hope you enjoy.
The universal need for expression in art lies…in man’s rational impulse to exalt the inner and outer world into a spiritual consciousness for himself, as an object in which he recognises his own self. He satisfies the need of this spiritual freedom when he makes all that exists explicit for himself within, and in a corresponding way realises this his explicit self without, evoking thereby, in this reduplication of himself, what is in him into vision and into knowledge for his own mind and that of others.
– G.W.F. Hegel
What do I mean by ‘legitimate’ here? Something is legitimate to us, in this sense, if there is some external validation of its existence by other persons or by an object that is independent of us, not just ourselves or our own impression of things. For example, suppose that at night I see a bright light flash across the sky that is unlike anything I have seen before, but I’m the only one who saw it. In situations like these, we feel torn because no one else was there to validate or invalidate our perception of this flash, nor can it be integrated into our prior beliefs. “Am I crazy, what was that?” you might think. We desire an explanation of this phenomenon because we are certain that it happened, that we saw something, but uncertain why and wish to settle it through some process of external validation. There are a couple of ways this could go. There could be an external explanation or an internal explanation, and it could be validated either by persons, or by further objects.
An ‘external’ explanation of such
a phenomenon is when something about the world (that is not us) explains it,
like that a large malfunctioning, satellite had recently been launched and
that’s what we had seen. This phenomenon would be validated for us through
persons if we were told this by other people or, for example, by the news, and
we accept their explanation. It would be validated for us through objects if,
for example, we saw it clearly the next day in daylight, and could tell that it
was a satellite and similar enough to what we saw that we can infer their
identity. An ‘internal’ explanation of such a phenomenon is when it is
something about us that explains it, like if there were something wrong
with our eyes such that we would be prone to visual hallucinations of light.
This would be validated for us through persons if, for example, an
ophthalmologist examined our eyes and told us about some problem. It would be
validated for us through objects if, for example, we looked in the mirror after
seeing the flash and our eyes were bloodshot and lazy, leading us to infer
something must be wrong with them.
(A simple example to keep this
distinction in mind is to think of a depressed person. The much-touted
“chemical imbalance” theory is an internal explanation whereas if someone is in
a terrible environment (e.g., at work or home), that would be an external
explanation for their depression. The person-object distinction only tracks the
method by which we come to accept such an explanation, if indeed we accept it.
Both methods, person and object, are ‘external’ in the former sense because we
always experience persons and objects as external to us and it is only through
the fact that they are external that they could provide validation at all. This
is because we must perceive them to be independent of us.)
Now take this supposed ocean of
subjectivity constitutive of ourselves – our complex and multifaceted inner
sense. The differences between this and the light example are numerous. Our
inner sense is ubiquitous, complex, and seemingly ineffable. It is ubiquitous
because we cannot escape the constant, flowing, multiplicity of thought and
memory streaming through us at any moment. This is because, insofar as we are
conscious, insofar as we are living at all, we can also be explicitly aware of ourselves
in this way. It is complex because our motives, beliefs and desires are often beyond
even concentrated and deliberate introspection. Our own subjectivity is often
opaque, even to ourselves. Finally, it appears ineffable because how we
actually are seems impossible to express in words, or even deeds. For
example, when someone goes through a personal tragedy, imagine what it would it
take for them to fully explain what they are feeling. We are always
attempting to do so but can never actually achieve it.
On the other hand, however, and
this is the key point: the conditions for the external validation of our inner
sense to us is exactly the same as the case of the flashing light. We still
desire some person, or some object, to provide external validation for our own
being. Otherwise, we are left thinking that our thoughts, feelings, and
emotions are mere subjective whimsy, something fundamentally cut off from the
world. And this point should not be alien to you. Every time you explain what
you are doing to someone else, every time you apologise to someone simply for
feeling a certain way, that is our desire for the external validation of our
inner sense manifesting itself. And it is not until we get such validation,
that we reach a point where we experience ourselves as legitimate, that we ever
satisfy our unquenching desire to feel at home in this world. When we do
achieve this experiential legitimation of ourselves, I call it self-consciousness.
This is what Hegel means, in the above quote, when he says that our spiritual
freedom is only satisfied when the inner is made explicit for ourselves in
objective expression.
II. Unfortunately, unlike
simple questions of everyday validity, our modes of communicating this supposed
inner sense are lacking. We are cursed as humans to try (and often fail) to
wedge as much of that internal flux through a fundamentally limited medium of
everyday expression. David Foster Wallace writes:
[It’s] as
though inside you is this enormous room full of what seems like everything in the
whole universe at one time or another and yet the only parts that get out have
to somehow squeeze out through one of those tiny keyholes you see under the
knob in older doors. As if we are all trying to see each other through these
tiny keyholes.
In this example, if successful, a
kind of validation is gained through persons because someone else, something
you experience as external and thus independent of you, successfully recognises
what you believe to be true about yourself, about your own inner sense. However,
in this essay I am not interested primarily in others. I am interested in the
fact that you can actually acquire validation through objects too. Even the
very process of talking about your inner sense is a process of objectifying
yourself into some form of externally available expression, an object that
could possibly validate our inner sense. That object is simply the thing you
say about yourself. Thus, it is not only for the sake of other’s validating
recognition of ourselves that we confide in others, but also for the sake of producing
an object through which we recognise ourselves, through the object that is our
speech. It is itself a manifestation of our desire for self-consciousness. This
thought is often expressed through the popular idea of ‘venting’, the idea that
merely by expressing our own inner sense we can somehow alleviate our own
distress.
However, the weakness with our
own expression being the object which is supposed to validate our inner sense,
is that it is still something that comes from ourselves and could still
therefore be the product of our own mere subjectivity, our own whimsy,
rather than something genuinely external to us. Indeed, the practice of venting
is often neither constructive, in that it offers no solutions, nor is totally
honest about ourselves and our situation, because we often bend the truth in
favour of a positive portrayal of ourselves. It becomes a flight of fancy.
Thus, it cannot properly play the role of an object that provides external
validation by itself because we know, implicitly or explicitly, that it merely
comes from us, not from something existing independently of us. It can only
play this role as a means of getting validation through others, but not by
virtue of itself. It also means that if others are not able to look beyond our
speech, beyond the surface, recognition through persons will not be possible
either. I argued in the last essay
in this series I argued that work (properly understood) was a way we
could achieve this through objects, but is there another kind of object that
can play this role?
III. Art is a special kind
of object. What seems to me to be the unique thing that it has, that no other (inanimate)
worldly entity has, is the potency of its expression. Now, I mean a very
specific thing by this. Consider the following passage from Werner Herzog’s The
Twilight World, where he describes the jungle:
There is one
unvarying constant: everything in the jungle is at pains to strangle everything
else in the battle for sunlight. It may be pitch-black at night, but nothing
changes the overwhelming implacable present tense of the jungle. Bird sound and
the shrill of crickets, as though a great locomotive had applied its emergency
brakes and were screaming uncontrollably along the rails, for hours and hours,
without stopping.
Now, I could have conveyed to you
the fact that the jungle is made up of a chaotic cacophony of competing
interests and constant noise by listing all of the organisms that live there
and their function, and that would all be very interesting. Or I could simply point
you to Herzog’s telling us that the jungle has an “overwhelming implacable
present tense”, and that says everything I could ever want to say about it, and
more. This is art’s potency.
You can see the same thing play
out in other mediums. For example, in Vertigo, Midge’s impotent and somewhat
pathetic externalisation of her desire for Scottie’s love through her painting (one of the most horrifying
scenes in all of cinema), says a million things about her character that no amount
of expository dialogue could have done better. Alternatively, one cannot help
but be struck by the vibrant, shimmering beauty and clarity of vision in Van
Gogh’s Cypresses.
We cannot explain ourselves into the effect it has on us, we cannot simply look
at a cypress tree, or a picture of one, and feel the same as we do when we
marvel at this masterwork.
How I like to describe this
potency is by saying that art is concentrated signification. Something
is ‘significant’ to us if it means something to us. For example, the sentence
“the sky is blue”, means to us that the thing we call the sky is so and so
colour (blue). However, everything in experience means something to us in the
sense I am thinking of. If I see that the door is open, it means that someone
is (probably) home. If I see a car hurtling towards me, it means I am in
danger. If I see that its raining, it means that I should not sit outside (if I
don’t want to get wet). When we experience art, it means something to us in
this way too. However, it differs in what I am calling, its concentration of
meaning.
I say that art’s meaning is
concentrated for two reasons. First, because art is rich with meaning in
a way that ordinary objects, ordinary speech, and ordinary actions, are not. (‘Ordinary’
here just mean any non-artistic object.) It is rich because when the elements
of a piece of art come together, they by far transcend the sum of those
elements; their joint expression goes beyond any cumulative effect of those
elements. The previous artistic examples are all cases of this. Herzog’s
description of the jungle is obviously not analysable into a list of organisms
that live in the jungle and what they do, nor some second-hand description of
it, it is more than that. One way of thinking about this is that art can
never adequately be summarised, either by its non-artistic elements
or by descriptions meant to represent those elements. Art-objects are unified and unable to be
decomposed without loss.
For example, tell someone “The
sky is blue” and they know all they need to know without looking at the sky. Such
a sentence just is the sum of its parts, and these parts we understand. It is
the simple transmission of information. Tell someone about your favourite novel
all you want but you will never have them know what it is to read the book,
without them actually reading the book. There is no simple transmission of
information in this case because an art-object is a unity encounterable only through
a particular spatiotemporal relationship with it. Merleau-Ponty summaries this
idea as follows:
In a picture
or a piece of music the idea is incommunicable by means other than the display
of colours and sounds. Any analysis of Cézanne’s work, if I have not seen his
pictures, leaves me with a choice between several possible Cézannes, and it is
the sight of the pictures which provides me with the only existing Cézanne, and
therein the analyses find their full meaning. The same is true of a poem or a
novel…[they] are individuals, that is, beings in which the expression is
indistinguishable from the thing expressed, their meaning, accessible only
through direct contact, being radiated with no change of their temporal and
spatial situation…[they are] a nexus of living meanings, not the law for a
certain number of covariant terms.
The same is true of our encounter
with other people. They are not a walking set of propositions, but a living
unity. Ditto for art.
Second, the meaning of a work of
art is concentrated because it is not something beyond the artwork itself. It
is sufficient unto itself. In the previous examples, we saw that many objects
have meaning for us as calls for action or inference about other parts of the
world, or for future aims. For example, the open door or the car coming towards
me. These ordinary objects, for the most part, point beyond themselves. Art, on
the other hand, is revealed to us as a self-standing entity whose meaning is
intrinsic to its existence, not some action or inference on our behalf. That
is, the meaning of a work of art does not point us beyond itself, but to
itself. (This is also true of people.)
Thus, an artwork, or creative entities
more generally, are both a potent form of expression, understood as something
having a special kind of richness for us, and being a special kind of
individual whole that transcends its constituent elements, that can only be
experienced in a proximal encounter with it.
IV. To tie the preceding
points together, my thought is as follows. We saw: (1) that we desire some
external validation of our inner sense, understood phenomenologically as
encountering something that that exists independently of us and adequately
represents our inner sense; (2) that the problem with ordinary objects playing
this role was that they often lacked the expressive capacity to sufficiently
represent it; and (3), that art-objects have a preternatural potency of
expression, beyond that of ordinary objects. The natural conclusion here, I
argue, is that art-objects can play the role of an object that legitimates our
inner sense through its expressive potency, filling the gap left by ordinary
expression. The hope is that some pieces of art are able to represent that
complex and ineffable inner sense we carry about ourselves, or the human
condition that we participate in, in such a way that they provide a
legitimating encounter. Therefore, making art a valuable source of self-consciousness.
The idea is as follows. Given the
right piece of art, the right qualities, and the relevant antecedent
experiences relating ourselves to it, we can find ourselves in a position where
it’s particular form of expression coincides completely with some part of us –
some idea, experience, feeling, or complex emotional state. That is to say, we
encounter an objective expression of that which was until then complex, ineffable,
and private. Thus, in this encounter, we would gain a kind of perceptual
knowledge of our own subjectivity through its reflection in art, which was
until then mere abstract and undefined thought, now externally available in the
world as an independent existent. It is knowledge specifically, and not a
projection of our mere subjectivity, because we know that the object exists
entirely independently of us, yet we still recognise our own subjectivity in
it. Thus, it fulfils the conditions for a legitimating encounter as it affirms
that which we thought we knew about ourselves through an external explanation,
through something that is independent of us but also expressive of us.
I think such encounters are possible
and actually happen, frequently. I can only attempt to prove such a conclusion
with reference to my own experience (and others I have talked to about this),
however I am nonetheless hoping it generalises.
Throughout my life, I have
encountered art and had a distinct kind of experience that elicits a particular
emotional-psychological response. It is a kind of titanic feeling that seems to
lay bare a particular aspect of myself, for myself. It is precisely this
feeling that provides a kind of phenomenological validation of my inner sense,
self-consciousness. It provides such self-consciousness in the same way that
the recognition
by others, or my own projects do. This is only possible because of art’s
potency, its ability to express meaning beyond that of a merely propositional
character, to somehow capture the complex and ineffable. It is the reciprocal
recognition of our inner sense, subjectivity, with art, an objective and
external thing. In these moments, art has allowed me a moment of sublimating my
desire for objective recognition, a moment in which the key is turned, and the door
through which ordinary expression is usually squeezed through, is swung wide
open. Let me try and give an example.
I find in poetry a fitting
presentation here for this kind of art. Many great poems, only spanning a few
lines, with little syntax to speak of, seem to profoundly capture something about
our own experience, or about the human condition we participate in,
intuitively, in a way that seems irreducible to any possible analysis of it.
William Carlos Williams’ poem This Is Just To Say is an excellent
example of this:
I have eaten
the plums
that were in
the icebox
and which
you were probably
saving
for breakfast
Forgive me
they were delicious
so sweet
and so cold
There is nothing particularly
notable at a ‘surface’ level about plums and the tender regret the narrator
imparts, in so few words. Still, in this small feat, Williams catches such a
specific and beautiful truth about relationships, the simple delights of life,
and the ways in which we love each other. (It is part of my account that it is
impossible to tell you what it expresses, just read it again if you want an
analysis!) I almost invariably tear up a little each time I seriously read it
as it expresses this so powerfully and wholly. That flux of incommunicable
feelings flows through me, fusing itself with the poem’s reality, mirroring it
almost perfectly. In reading it, I encounter and validate my own inner sense in
a way that would not have been possible otherwise. The scene from Vertigo I
mentioned earlier is another perfect example of this.
I hope this shows that the idea
is not so unfamiliar. Indeed, I think it is not so different from the popular notion
that we can “feel seen” by something. This idea gets at something very like
what I am saying. While this is often said in silly or trivial situations, the
recognition of oneself, the having of a validating encounter with the world is
neither silly nor trivial. It is a valuable source of self-consciousness. The kind of art
experience I am talking about is a much more potent form of this. It expresses that which you know, at least implicitly, about yourself, that could otherwise not have been said.
In fact, I would go as far to say
that some of the greatest art is great in virtue of this possibility. While
there is great art that functions as pure entertainment or spectacle, as an
exploration of ideas, a formal or stylistic showcase, a moral statement, or as
a monument of sublimity, I find that those artists whose work repeatedly
beguiles us with images of our own subjectivity leaves the strongest impression
on me. For example, I see Ingmar Bergman embarking on a project such as this.
His films explore complex psychological themes and dynamics between subjects where
sincere empathic engagement is rewarded by laying specific aspects of human
mental life bare, through its expression of the human condition that we all
participate in. On paper, this might not sound like such a good thing,
especially if they express the parts of yourself you dislike or anguish over. But
the catharsis of feeling seen and recognised at a deep subjective level by the
art is incredibly therapeutic because it orients us in the right way towards
our actual selves and thus our actual possibilities. (Otherwise, we are wont to
retreat to a dishonest, but more easily acceptable, fantasy.)
This is a good thing because, if I am right, it is just another form of
self-consciousness.
For me, the power and pleasure of
experiencing these art forms is that they are concrete externalisations of utterly
familiar yet always inexpressible inner sense. This encounter with art effects the
reconciliation of ourselves with the world, fulfilling our desire to validate ourselves
as legitimate, objective, and self-conscious individuals in and amongst the
world, not a mere psychic addition.
V. I have been writing so
far as if there were this simple relationship between our inner sense, which
stays the same, and our encounter with an artwork that expresses it. However,
this is not exactly what is happening. This encounter is not mere confirmation
for us, of some fact about ourselves. It is an instance of self-consciousness. Self-consciousness
is just knowledge of ourselves. However, as I note in the previous essay in
this series (section VI), self-consciousness is not this simple relationship between our
self, which stays the same, and our state of knowledge which seeks out this
static self. This is because there is no distinction between ourselves and our
state of knowledge. This means that a validating encounter with an art-object
is not merely ourselves encountering something we recognise as genuinely
expressive of ourselves. It means that such an encounter creates ourselves
anew, as one who is more than what they were before, as one who further
recognises what they are, their own possibilities, and thus, their freedom. In
this sense, the art-encounter can be more than merely expressive of us, but constitutive of
us.
No comments:
Post a Comment