Unius: ...another benefit of physicalism is that it
is more parsimonious than dualism.
Dualis: So what if it is parsimonious? It denies something
that is undeniable: the existence of conscious experience.
Unius: Seriously? How many times do I have to say
that I am not denying that we have conscious experience? I am just
saying that it does not require an autonomous realm of entities to be
postulated in order to explain it. Our awareness of the world is physical—just
like everything else!
Dualis: Yeah, okay, you say that, but...you know what,
whatever, we've had this debate a thousand times. Let's talk about something
else. What were you saying about parsimony?
Unius: Okay, sure. All I meant was: putting our
explanatory differences aside, would you not admit, at least, that
considerations of parsimony count in favour of physicalism?
Dualis: What do you mean? I don't care if something is
parsimonious if it denies something fundamental.
Unius: I know, I know, but is it not at least regrettable that
you must postulate two kinds of fundamental entity, rather than one? Should we
not prefer, if we know absolutely nothing else about two theories, the simpler
one?
Dualis: I suppose I kind of see what you mean. However, if
I did admit that it was 'regrettable' that I cannot postulate one kind of
entity instead of two, it would only be in some very abstract sense.
Unius: What do you mean?
Dualis: Well, we both agree there must be physical
entities, right?
Unius: Sure.
Dualis: Our difference is that I also think that
conscious experience is a phenomenon that cannot be denied.
Unius: I don't disagree with that, conscious experience is
just not what you think it is.
Dualis: So our difference is that I think that the fact of
conscious experience requires us to postulate a different kind of entity in
order to explain it, and you don't?
Unius: That seems right.
Dualis: But then, to go back to your question, it makes no
sense to say that I 'regret' that I have to postulate another kind of
fundamental entity—because I think it must be postulated to explain something,
consciousness. It would be 'regrettable' if we were in a world that did not
have conscious experience as part of it, but that is trivial because there
would be nothing there for me to explain. And I would regret it not because it
is less parsimonious but because in such a world I would see no need to
postulate it, no reason. This is just as you, contra me, see no
need to postulate it in this world.
Unius: But think of all the problems with postulating two kinds
of fundamental entity, rather than one! How are these entities supposed to
interact? What is the relationship between the 'mental' objects of our
perception, and the physical objects that are related or correspond to them?
And if the mental is not there in the most fundamental entities, but only
emerges at a certain level of physical complexity, how is it supposed to
'emerge out of' the physical?
Dualis: Woah, woah, woah. Look, I understand that there are
problems with dualism, but none of the points you raise have anything to do
with parsimony. Sure, they have to do with postulating two specified kinds of
entity, rather than one, and they pose a strong explanatory burden upon those
who do so. But the problems are not there in virtue of the position's ontological
profligacy, the number of kinds of entities it postulates. Rather, they are
there by virtue of the nature of the kinds of entities postulated. No dualist
will deny that there are notorious difficulties in reconciling the two.
Unius: I don't know, it sounds like you are admitting the
point. One kind of entity faces less explanatory burden than the other. Hence
we should prefer a theory that postulates less fundamental entities because of
the problems with their multiplication.
Dulias: I understand what you just said, and I even agree
with you. But that is a different point to the one you gave above. Earlier you
said that parsimony by itself and independent of the content of the theory,
independent of the perceived phenomena in need of explanation, and
therefore independent of the difficulties of reconciling the
co-existence of different kinds of fundamental entities, counts in favour
of one theory. Now you are saying that there are some real difficulties in
reconciling two specific kinds of fundamental entity with each other, given
their nature. Once again, this is something no dualist would deny.
Unius: And you don't regret these difficulties?
Dualis: Are you even listening to me? What I ought to
regret is relative to what phenomena I think is in need of explanation, to my explanatory paradigm. Any regrets I should feel about
dualism's difficulties are silenced by the fact that I think I must postulate
mental entities. Any regret I feel would be irrational in that regard.
Unius: I see what you are getting at, but I am not
convinced that there is not some intrinsic connection with a lower count for
one's ontological kinds and true metaphysical system, even abstracted from a
particular theory or explanatory paradigm.
Dualis: Maybe if I put it like this: Suppose I say to you
that you have two theories to choose from. On the first theory, only the
physical exists. On the second theory, nothing exists. And I don't mean (the)
nothing, or 'the void', or anything like that. I mean literally that there is
no existence whatsoever. What theory do you prefer?
Unius: This is getting a little facetious.
Dualis: Seriously. What theory would you prefer.
Unius: Obviously I prefer the first.
Dualis: Why?
Unius:...Because something obviously exists, whatever
that existence happens to be. We cannot choose the second theory because it
does not explain that fact.
Dualis: But would you agree that the second theory is more
parsimonious than the first?
Unius: I guess so.
Dualis: But doesn't parsimony count for something? Is it
not regrettable that you couldn't say there is nothing instead of something?
Unius: I see. I suppose what you are saying is that
invoking parsimony here is a little ridiculous, given we could not be having
this conversation if there were nothing at all.
Dualis: Indeed. But more precisely: explanatory necessity
silences parsimony as an ontological consideration. It is not just another thing to 'weigh up' against things, it is utterly relative to one's explanatory paradigm. What it is like for parsimony to be invoked here, against the view that something exists rather than nothing, is what it feels for me when you invoke parsimony against dualism. It just does not make sense to wield Ockham's razor against those that reject your presuppositions about what counts as whether some entity is beyond
(explanatory) necessity.
Unius: I think I might agree with you then. Though what do
you mean by 'explanatory paradigm'? We've been saying it but I'm not really
clear about what you mean.
Dualis: Just what the intuitive idea would suggest. From
your explanatory perspective it makes sense for you to think that the mental
can be shaved off of our ontology by Ockham's razor, considerations of
parsimony, only because you do not think it is actually doing any explanatory
work. But that is precisely our disagreement: whether it does explanatory work.
I think it does. That is why it cannot be a consideration for me. In this sense,
we have a different explanatory paradigm.
Unius: Right. Could you be a little more precise?
Dualis: Sure. Suppose that physicalism is one theory T1 and
dualism is another T2. From your perspective T2 just is T1
plus another kind of entity, call it X. Therefore, T2 = T1 + X. Your view about
X, as an entity, is that it is explanatorily superfluous. You see no reason to
postulate it, and you therefore should not do so (given what you believe).
Therefore, you have a straightforward application of Ockham's razor to the two
views. My view about X, as an entity, is that it is explanatorily necessary. We
must postulate it if we are to explain the phenomenon of the world. Therefore,
I cannot apply Ockham's razor to the two theories. Here is the key though: how
do you think we are to resolve this dispute?
Unius: Well, it can't be solved through Ockham's razor, by
an appeal to parsimony,
Dualis: And why not?
Unius: I follow you. Because we each have a different view
about the dispensability of entity X. Therefore, it is that we
should be arguing about, the dispensability of some entity and it's role
in explaining some phenomena.
Dualis: Exactly.
Unius: I mean, I suppose the lesson is basically that we
should just go back to arguing directly about the actual issue about what
explanations are necessary and what are not. It seems to me that the way you just outlined
your version of Ockham's razor is what we were already doing, if only
implicitly: keeping things that are necessary and getting rid of things that
are unnecessary, then going on to argue with others about the scope of that
(explanatory) necessity. In fact, Ockham's razor seems already to be expressed this way by its most common rendering: "do not multiply entities beyond necessity", as
long as "beyond necessity" is interpreted as "beyond explanatory
necessity."
Dualis: Yeah, I think that's right. And I think
that's all metaphysics really is, or ever was, or perhaps just should be.
Unius: So...I guess that leaves us back where we started.
Dualis: It does, but at least we can stop arguing about parsimony now...
Unius: True that. Did you see Chalmers' new argument for
panprotopsychism? He calls it the 'Twombie Schwampman.'
Dualis: Incredible.
My proposal is the following. We should read "other things being equal" strictly, as indicating that both theories explain the exact same phenomena, in the exact same way, but that the latter theory posits further entities that do not explain any further phenomena. That is to say, in situations where T2 is just T1 + X, and X is some entity or type of entity playing no explanatory role, it is rational to prefer T1. Thus, "other things being equal" means "explanatorily equivalent." While this is a rather narrow scope for the principle, I think this is its proper place. This is because I do not think some theory is automatically superior to some other theory just because it has fewer entities. What matters is whether those entities are doing explanatory work. Ontological profligacy is entirely justified insofar as that profligacy is taken to be necessary to explain some feature of the world, some phenomenon.
This
simply means that, given the choice between two theories that are exactly the
same, except that one posits some further entity that plays no explanatory
role, we should accept the theory that does not posit these further entities.
It says that we should not postulate entities unnecessarily, that is, for
no reason. If an entity is postulated for no reason, we should not accept
that it exists.
III. We can see the appeal of such a principle with an example.
Suppose Lachlan smashes a window. This is an event. Now suppose I argued that
the natural explanation we would give of the window being smashed was all
correct. Lachlan kicked a ball and it hitting the window was sufficient to
break it. Now suppose I argue that simultaneous with the football hitting the
window, a God decided to smash the window using telekinesis. No explanatory
demand is fulfilled by such an appeal because everything would have happened as
it did without God, especially given I am not replacing the causal power of the
ball as the thing smashing the window with God smashing the window but instead
supplementing it with God. In this case, I would surely be wrong to
postulate further entities (this God) because no phenomena are accounted for
that were not accounted for before. In other words, I am postulating an entity
for no explanatory reason. I am just arbitrarily supposing there is
something else there. It is arbitrary because I could postulate any number of
other entities or mechanisms to have caused this event, even though they would
not further explain anything.
Arbitrariness
is objectionable in metaphysics because it amounts to arguing that we should
postulate entities for no reason, which would trivialise the whole endeavour.
Suppose we were to ask someone who postulates such a God in the above
situation, or any other entity doing no explanatory work, why they do so. Given
they play no explanatory role, could a satisfactory reason be given? They
cannot say “because it explains so and so phenomena”, because so and so
phenomena have already been explained by their ontology. They cannot say
“because it is useful to suppose that it exists” because just because something
is useful does not mean it exists. And surely, if one cannot give a reason for
why we should accept a posit, then we should not accept it.
If
some stranger came up to you and asked if you could give them $100, and when
you asked why, they reply “oh, for no reason” (and you somehow knew this was
true), should the onus be on you to give a reason why you should not give them
the money? No, the onus is on them. And if they proffer no reason (and you come
up with no reason yourself), then you have no reason to give them money. The
same burden holds for arbitrary metaphysics. If someone postulates some entity,
the burden is on them to show why it is necessary to explain some phenomenon.
Denying this principle would amount to arguing that we should postulate
entities for no reason, which surely trivialises the whole endeavour because
then, anything goes.
To
summarise: we are justified in applying Ockham's razor when choosing between theories
that are explanatorily equivalent but one postulates entities that explain
nothing further. We are justified in eliminating entities that play no
explanatory role, or, we are rational to choose the theory that lacks those
entities, because we have no positive reason to accept them. If there is no
reason to accept that some entity exists, then we should not do so.
This
is not to say I am not open to indispensability arguments, arguments that are
trying to meet some explanatory burden, or transcendental arguments for
necessary metaphysical structures. These are of a different structure to the
kind of situations I am considering here. These kinds of arguments do give a
positive reason why they are to be taken seriously. For example, Plato thought
that his Forms made possible what he took to be the undeniable intelligibility
of worldly entities. Heidegger thinks that a transcendental argument can be
made from the revealing (individuation) of intelligible individual beings to
the existence of the nothing. I think a transcendental argument can be made for
the existence of a real duration to explain something I take to be undeniable:
the perception of change. Thus, another way of thinking about what I am saying
when I say that entities should not be multiplied beyond explanatory necessity
is to think about its negation: entities should be postulated according to
explanatory necessity.
IV. Why should this be the approach we take with regard to Ockham's
razor, other than avoiding the kind of arbitrariness I point out above? Is it
not kind of narrow? The main reason why we should endorse this kind of
parsimony is that it pushes debates back to the substantive issue at hand,
rather than to a kind of meta-ontological point-scoring, typical of analytic
metaphysics. Indeed, the reason we should take this narrow approach is that
virtually any other application of Ockham's razor will always
be an objectionable kind of meta-ontological point scoring. What do I mean by
this? I can show this with an example.
Take
the debate between physicalists and dualists. It is sometimes said that one of
the theoretical advantages of physicalism is that it is more parsimonious than
dualism. This is because physicalists think that there is only one type of
fundamental entity, the physical, and dualists think there are two types of
fundamental entity, the physical and the mental. In other words, it is
sometimes said that physicalism countenancing fewer types of entities than
dualism is a reason, by itself, to prefer it to dualism. However, why should we
think that the number of types of entities by itself tells us about whether
some theory is true? The example in the above dialogue, of a theory that
postulates nothing versus one that postulates something, is supposed to show
this. If we are not given a further reason for why each type of entity is
supposed to exist, then the number, by itself, provides nothing. Couched purely
in terms of parsimony, the debate cannot be made sense of from this abstract
position. Couched in terms of explanatory necessity, however, we can make
perfect sense of it.
The
reason dualists postulate two types of entity is to explain two types of
phenomena that we observe and which are in need of explanation: the 'outside'
world, which seems to have shape, structure, and dimensionality, and our
experience of that world, which seems to be of a different kind, something to
which it appears to be a category error to ask: "what is the width and
depth of your perception right now?" Not only this, the dualist thinks it
is virtually impossible to deny that there exists this thing, consciousness,
that is something above and beyond the physical world. This means that, for a
dualist, the fact that physicalists do not accept the mental
as something existing is a decisive reason against preferring
physicalism. And so it should be if you accept their views about what is in need of explanation. The relative parsimony of the alternative is
utterly silent in the face of the fact that, according to dualists,
physicalism fails to explain something we cannot deny, the
reality of the mental. In this situation, it is not merely that the dualist
'weighed up' considerations of explanatory adequacy and parsimony, finding the
former to outweigh the latter. Rather, the dualist thinks that the more
parsimonious theory fails to live up to an explanatory task, which ultimately
silences its parsimony as a real consideration for it. That is to say, it does
not make sense to apply Ockham's razor against the mental, for the dualist,
because its multiplication of entities is not beyond necessity.
Of
course, the physicalist will disagree that there are both types of entity. They
will say that the seeming discrepancy between these phenomena, the external
world and our experience of it, is illusory. Both the outside world and our
experience of it are fundamentally the same kind of thing. They are both
physical. However, they will not say this because their view
is more parsimonious, but because they think that postulating
an extra class of entities to explain the mental is explanatorily superfluous.
The mental can be fully explained by recourse to the physical. They will
attempt to show this with arguments independent of parsimony because parsimony
by itself cannot show this. This means the choice between theories for a
physicalist is then straightforwardly a case where Ockham's razor, as
formulated above, applies. Dualism is just physicalism plus X, where X is doing
no explanatory work. However, its use in no way rests on the relative parsimony
between theories, but on the explanatory necessity of postulating them.
We
can now see how this pushes us back to the actual debate, rather than towards
meta-ontological point scoring, because at no point does either party appeal to
parsimony to argue for their theory. We can see this by paying careful
attention to where the disagreement actually lies for each side of the debate.
What they disagree about is whether some phenomenon must be explained by the
postulation of another kind of entity. In this case, whether conscious
experience is something that must be explained by the postulation of
non-physical entities. Once this is settled (if it ever were), then we know whether
we can apply Ockham's razor or not (where the physicalist thinks we can and the
dualist thinks we cannot). But for this to be settled, then arguments must be
made for or against the explanatory necessity of postulating it, not at the
abstract level of parsimony. In other words, to know whether Ockham's razor
applies to a choice between theories, one must simply argue about the
tenability of the theories themselves, not the meta-ontological 'virtue' of
parsimony. In this case, the fact that physicalism is more parsimonious
than dualism is completely silent to the dualist because it refuses to explain
something that requires it.
It
might be objected that counting 2 types of entity is somehow 'more arbitrary'
than 1. If we can accept 2 types of entity, then why are there not 3 or 4
types? And so on. But this will not work. First, such an argument no longer has
to do with parsimony, it has to do with arbitrariness. Second, if we are
evaluating a theory purely on the number of types of fundamental entities
it accepts, 1 type of entity is exactly as arbitrary as any other number. What
makes a certain number of types of entity non-arbitrary is the explanatory role
they play. Peirce postulated 3 fundamental categories of being and he had an
explanation for why each was necessary. Just because there are
3 categories rather than 1 or 2 does not license the use of Ockham's razor
against his view, nor make it arbitrary. Rather, what matters is whether or not
he was right about their necessity, whether or not his arguments for it are
sound. The same is true for Plotinus' 4 ascending categories of being. As
arbitrary as 4—taken in the abstract—may seem, and as wrong as he may be about them, each layer
explains some phenomena and is argued for in that regard. Ockham's razor does not
automatically cut against the system absent a response to those arguments. Nor, in fact, does arbitrariness, because the whole point of any system is that its constituents are non-arbitrary.
(The perceived weakness of such extravagant systems is that they they must proffer convincing arguments for each and every postulated type of being, as well as their mutual co-existence and relation. That is what makes such a system seem arbitrary, as at least one of their posits, or the relations between them, are bound to seem superfluous or unworkable to any given person. Conversely, the weakness (and task) of an austere system is to show how all the things that are in seeming need of ontological explanation, can really be wholly explained in terms of something else, thereby rendering them superfluous.)
We
can also see how virtually any other application of the razor is objectionable.
This is because there are only two options for some proposed entity: either it
is deemed explanatorily necessary, or it is not. If it is, then it cannot be eliminated by considerations of parsimony, and if it is not, then there is no reason to postulate it. In the former case, Ockham's razor does not apply. In the
latter, it is the fact that there is no reason to postulate the entity in one's
theorising, not that not doing so would make it more parsimonious, that makes the theory without it preferable. In both cases mere simplicity is irrelevant.
V. What this points to is that there is a certain relativity to the
use of Ockham's razor, as I have proposed it. Whether it applies in a
particular case for a particular philosopher will be relative to what phenomena
one thinks is in need of some special explanatory posit. Suppose we call this
one's 'explanatory paradigm', which describes (1) those things one thinks are
in need of explanation, and of those things, (2) which of them require
postulating entities to explain them. Ockham's razor is therefore the principle
that says you should not postulate entities beyond what your explanatory
paradigm circumscribes. Disagreements about whether something should fall
within our explanatory paradigm cannot be resolved at the level of the count of
those things, but only at the level of settling the explanatory paradigm
itself, at the level of first deciding on, or arguing about, (1) and (2). We
discovered this through our analysis of the debate between physicalists and
dualists, and I would argue it applies to all other metaphysical debates. It is
here we encounter what is the ultimate task of metaphysics: to determine what
needs to be explained, how to explain it, and what counts as an explanation for
it. A proper appreciation of this version of Ockham's razor orients us towards
this ultimate task.
No comments:
Post a Comment